Logo - springer
Slogan - springer

Social Sciences - Applied Ethics & Social Responsibility | Ethical Theory and Moral Practice - incl. option to publish open access

Ethical Theory and Moral Practice

Ethical Theory and Moral Practice

An International Forum

Editor-in-Chief: A.W. Musschenga; F.R. Heeger

ISSN: 1386-2820 (print version)
ISSN: 1572-8447 (electronic version)

Journal no. 10677

VIRTUAL ISSUE No. 1: Virtues, Skills, and Moral Expertise

ETMP has decided to launch a series of ‘virtual special issues’. Virtual special issues are online-only collections of articles, already published in the journal. Virtual special issues are especially useful for readers searching for material on specific topics.

This first virtual special issue brings together six articles, published between 2005 and 2013, that discuss the skill model of virtue. Virtues are commonly defined as positive moral qualities, desirable character traits, or as dispositions to make the right choices in particular situations. None of these definitions provide much insight, neither in the nature of virtues nor in the nature of moral education. Since all humans have at least basic skills such as driving a car, riding a bicycle, and cooking, and perhaps also more specialized skills such as playing piano, chess, and soccer, all know what it takes to have and to acquire skills, and can therefore get a better understanding of what it means to have and acquire virtues.
Those who have skills in particular domains are usually called experts. This explains the tendency to regard morally skilled persons – the fully virtuous – also as experts. Expertise has the interest of psychologists and specialists in Artificial Intelligence. Philosophers writing on expertise often find the work of Hubert and Stuart Dreyfus on the phenomenology of moral expertise (Dreyfus & Dreyfus 1991, 2004) useful for fleshing out the skill model of virtue. References to their work appear in almost all articles in this collection.
The articles are ordered chronologically. In his first article Daniel Jacobson goes into the perceptual moral epistemology which is characteristic for virtue ethics. Influential proponents of virtue ethics often claim that virtuous persons possess moral knowledge which issues from a distinctive sensibility which allows them ‘to see what to do,’ through their properly trained emotional responses. Jacobson attempts to vindicate virtue ethics’ perceptual moral epistemology by drawing on the epistemology associated with the skill model. Contemporary virtue ethics, says Jacobson, accepts one the one hand the skill model. On the other hand it stresses that virtues require a strong conception of practical wisdom for dealing with conflicts between virtues. However, any conception of practical wisdom robust enough to resolve such conflicts cannot plausibly be considered a skill.
Two articles in this collection are from Matt Stichter. In the first one he argues, against Julia Annas (1995, 2003) that Aristotle does not reject the skill model of virtue, although his account of the structure of skill is different from that of Socrates. Stichter characterizes Socrates’ model as intellectualist, while the model of Aristotle is more empiricist. Referring to the work of Hubert and Stuart Dreyfus, Stichter contends that the empiricist model aligns better with recent research on expertise.
Virtue ethics states that those actions are morally right which should be chosen by experts in matters of virtue. But how to recognize a moral expert? What are their credentials? Traditional accounts of moral expertise contend that it is distinctive of moral experts that they give reliably correct moral advice, supported by adequate justification. According to Michael Cholbi this account is too lean because it allows for the possibility of moral experts who are not inclined to follow their own advice. Instead of two, three credentials identify the conditions for moral expertise. However, they are not very helpful for determining which individuals satisfy these conditions.
If the non-virtuous cannot be told to follow the advice of a fully virtuous person because they are unable to identify experts in virtue, what remains to be done for them is morally improve themselves. The kinds of action one needs to engage in when trying to improve oneself, such as self-monitoring, are not actions that any virtuous person would need to take. According to Robert Johnson (2003), any account of right action grounded in the virtues must make room for a genuine moral obligation to improve one’s character. Rosalind Hursthouse’s account of right action (Hursthouse 2000, 2006), says Johnson, fails to make room for self-improving actions. In his second article, Matt Stichter goes into this issue and argues that the skill model of virtue as developed by Hubert and Stuart Dreyfus provides support for Johnson’s thesis that the actions of the non-virtuous will differ from those of the virtuous.
Not only the character virtues, but also the intellectual virtue of practical wisdom can be understood as skill. (Practical) wisdom is the subject of James Swartwood’s article. Wisdom is for him the expert skill to make decisions in complex situations. Referring to psychological studies on the Recognition-Primed Decision model, Swartwood describes expert skill as a set of abilities. Experts have, e.g., the intuitive ability to identify quickly, effortless, and without conscious deliberation what ought to be done. But they are also good at conscious deliberation, and at identifying when and how to rely on intuition and deliberation. Swartwood thinks that his account of the expert skill model provides a resolution to the debate between Annas and Stichter in his first article. The expert skill model shows that wisdom had both a substantive intuitive (Stichter) and a substantive deliberative and meta-cognitive component (Annas).
The last article, by Robert Reed, does not see expert skills as a model for understanding every day ethical expertise. Everyday ethical expertise, says Reed, requires an openness to an experience of self-doubt very different from that involved in becoming an expert in other skills. Unlike driving or playing chess – examples used by Dreyfus and Dreyfus – moral intuitions cannot be refined without placing, not just one’s understanding of the situation, but one’s very self in question. Virtue shows itself, says Reed, chiefly in the genuineness of our ‘ethical expertise’ as we become more self-knowledgeable. Reed refers not the psychological literature, but to the work of Emanuel Levinas.
The skill model is a useful, but not generally accepted, tool for understanding the concept of virtue. A rival conception is that of virtue as disposition. The objection to the skill model is that experts are not necessary motivated to follow their own advices while fully virtuous person are. Swartwood mentions this objection, but thinks it does not undermine the expert model. Cholbi’s solution is to make the motivational requirement a condition for moral expertise. Another weak point in the expert skill model is that it does not do justice to the ordinary meaning of a expert as someone with specialized skills and knowledge. I do not favor calling the everyday moral competence of normally maturated moral individuals ‘moral expertise’, as Dreyfus and Dreyfus do. Many psychologists studying expertise stress that expertise is domain-specific. Although talk of the moral domain is quite common, its scope seems too all-encompassing for qualifying as a domain of expertise as understood by psychologists.
Albert W. Musschenga

References 

Annas J (1995) Virtue as a skill. Int J Philos Stud 3(2):227–243
Annas J (2003) The structure of virtue. In: DePaul M, Zagzebski L (eds) Intellectual virtue. Clarendon,
Oxford, UK pp15–33
Dreyfus H, Dreyfus S (1991) Towards a phenomenology of ethical expertise. Hum Stud 14:229–250
Dreyfus H, Dreyfus S (2004) The ethical implications of the five-stage skill-acquisition model. Bull Sci
Technol Soc 24(3):251–264
Hursthouse R (2000) On Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Hursthouse R (2006) Practical wisdom: a mundane account. Proc Aristot Soc 106(1):285–309
Johnson R (2003) Virtue and Right. Ethics 113:810–834

Seeing by Feeling: Virtues, Skills, and Moral Perception 

Daniel Jacobson

Ethical Expertise: The Skill Model of Virtue 

Matt Stichter

Moral Expertise and the Credentials Problem 

Michael Cholbi

Virtues, Skills, and Right Action 

Matt Stichter

Wisdom as an Expert Skill 

Jason D. Swartwood

Euthyphro’s Elenchus Experience: Ethical Expertise and Self-Knowledge 

Robert C. Reed

 

Articles

For authors and editors

  • Aims and Scope

    Aims and Scope

    Close

    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice: An International Forum is a peer-reviewed journal which aims to publish the best work produced in all fields of ethics. It welcomes high quality submissions regardless of the tradition or school of thought from which they derive. As an editorial priority, however, presentations should be accessible to the philosophical community at large.

    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice seeks interdisciplinary cooperation between ethics, theology and empirical disciplines such as medicine, economics, sociology, psychology and law. It recognises that distinctions between theory and practice are, to a large extent, artificial. The journal therefore aims to publish theoretically relevant 'practical' ethics and practically relevant 'theoretical' ethics.

  • Submit Online
  • Open Choice - Your Way to Open Access
  • Instructions for Authors
  • Author Academy: Training for Authors
  • Copyright information

    Copyright information

    Close

    Copyright Information

    For Authors

    Submission of a manuscript implies: that the work described has not been published before (except in form of an abstract or as part of a published lecture, review or thesis); that it is not under consideration for publication elsewhere; that its publication has been approved by all co-authors, if any, as well as – tacitly or explicitly – by the responsible authorities at the institution where the work was carried out.

    Author warrants (i) that he/she is the sole owner or has been authorized by any additional copyright owner to assign the right, (ii) that the article does not infringe any third party rights and no license from or payments to a third party is required to publish the article and (iii) that the article has not been previously published or licensed. The author signs for and accepts responsibility for releasing this material on behalf of any and all co-authors. Transfer of copyright to Springer (respective to owner if other than Springer) becomes effective if and when a Copyright Transfer Statement is signed or transferred electronically by the corresponding author. After submission of the Copyright Transfer Statement signed by the corresponding author, changes of authorship or in the order of the authors listed will not be accepted by Springer.

    The copyright to this article, including any graphic elements therein (e.g. illustrations, charts, moving images), is assigned for good and valuable consideration to Springer effective if and when the article is accepted for publication and to the extent assignable if assignability is restricted for by applicable law or regulations (e.g. for U.S. government or crown employees).

    The copyright assignment includes without limitation the exclusive, assignable and sublicensable right, unlimited in time and territory, to reproduce, publish, distribute, transmit, make available and store the article, including abstracts thereof, in all forms of media of expression now known or developed in the future, including pre- and reprints, translations, photographic reproductions and microform. Springer may use the article in whole or in part in electronic form, such as use in databases or data networks for display, print or download to stationary or portable devices. This includes interactive and multimedia use and the right to alter the article to the extent necessary for such use.

    Authors may self-archive the Author's accepted manuscript of their articles on their own websites. Authors may also deposit this version of the article in any repository, provided it is only made publicly available 12 months after official publication or later. He/she may not use the publisher's version (the final article), which is posted on SpringerLink and other Springer websites, for the purpose of self-archiving or deposit. Furthermore, the Author may only post his/her version provided acknowledgement is given to the original source of publication and a link is inserted to the published article on Springer's website. The link must be accompanied by the following text: "The final publication is available at link.springer.com".

    Prior versions of the article published on non-commercial pre-print servers like arXiv.org can remain on these servers and/or can be updated with Author's accepted version. The final published version (in pdf or html/xml format) cannot be used for this purpose. Acknowledgement needs to be given to the final publication and a link must be inserted to the published article on Springer's website, accompanied by the text "The final publication is available at link.springer.com". Author retains the right to use his/her article for his/her further scientific career by including the final published journal article in other publications such as dissertations and postdoctoral qualifications provided acknowledgement is given to the original source of publication.

    Author is requested to use the appropriate DOI for the article. Articles disseminated via link.springer.com are indexed, abstracted and referenced by many abstracting and information services, bibliographic networks, subscription agencies, library networks, and consortia.

    For Readers

    While the advice and information in this journal is believed to be true and accurate at the date of its publication, neither the authors, the editors, nor the publisher can accept any legal responsibility for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher makes no warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein.

    All articles published in this journal are protected by copyright, which covers the exclusive rights to reproduce and distribute the article (e.g., as offprints), as well as all translation rights. No material published in this journal may be reproduced photographically or stored on microfilm, in electronic data bases, video disks, etc., without first obtaining written permission from the publisher (respective the copyright owner if other than Springer). The use of general descriptive names, trade names, trademarks, etc., in this publication, even if not specifically identified, does not imply that these names are not protected by the relevant laws and regulations.

    Springer has partnered with Copyright Clearance Center's RightsLink service to offer a variety of options for reusing Springer content. For permission to reuse our content please locate the material that you wish to use on link.springer.com or on springerimages.com and click on the permissions link or go to copyright.com, then enter the title of the publication that you wish to use. For assistance in placing a permission request, Copyright Clearance Center can be connected directly via phone: +1-855-239-3415, fax: +1-978-646-8600, or e-mail: info@copyright.com.


    © Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

Alerts for this journal

 

Get the table of contents of every new issue published in Ethical Theory and Moral Practice.